
Back to alternative history
Contents
1. Preface
2. Spinoza's World, 1664
3. The Sabbateans
4. The Disputation
5. The Holy Land
6. Marriage
7. Common Prayer
8. America
9. Gottfried and Sophia
10. The Sublime Porte
11. Spinoza's World, 1691
12. Mustafa and the Janissaries
13. Naomi
14. Regime Change
15. Tulips
16. Twilight
17. Spinoza's World, 1712
18. Epilogue
Appendix
|
Spinoza in Turkey |
---|
"Therefore, that state is the freest whose laws are founded on
sound reason, so that every member of it may, if he will, be
free; that is, live with full consent under the entire guidance
of reason." -- Spinoza, Theological and Political Treatise,
16:58 |
|
Part 11 - Spinoza's World, 1691 |
1691 saw the death of both a Sultan and a Grand Vizier. The weak
and sickly Suleiman II was the first to go, succumbing early in
the year and being succeeded by his brother Ahmed II. Fazil
Pasha lived only a few months longer, falling in battle at
Slankamen in Serbia on August 19. [FN1]
These changes, momentous as they were, had little effect on
Spinoza. Like his predecessor, Ahmed II had spent most of his
life confined in the palace, and had little skill at politics.
There was another Kprl to occupy the Grand Vizier's chair,
however, and the Sultan himself was a cultured man who wrote
poetry, spoke Persian and Arabic, and considered himself a
philosopher. Under the rule of these enlightened men, Spinoza
remained in favor at court, and his university continued to
receive royal patronage.
|
|
Spinoza had little time for conversation with the Sultan. At the
age of fifty-nine, he was still quite capable of working a full
day; he taught classes at the university, held regular prayer
services and lectures at his home, attended to the business of
the Rational millet, and exchanged letters with 200-odd
correspondents throughout the civilized world. [FN2] His wife
Sarah, now a matron approaching forty, also maintained a thriving
correspondence with educated women throughout Europe, busied
herself in the practice of medicine, and had recently completed a
Ladino novel about the second wife of Maimonides. [FN3] Naomi,
at fourteen, was also expanding her creative horizons, playing
the flute at the Rational Synagogue and already beginning to
write hymns.
As the titular leader and continuing philosopher to a community
that now numbered more than thirty-five thousand, regularly
received communications from the four corners of the earth. From
England, there were hopeful tidings of the events that had
followed the Glorious Revolution and its accompanying Bill of
Rights. Many members of the small Rational Jewish community in
England had been apprehensive about the accession of William III,
who, as Stadtholder of the Netherlands, had once banned Spinoza's
works. The political pressures that had led to him doing so,
however, were not present in England, where the strict Calvinism
of the Dutch did not prevail and where a spirit of free inquiry
flourished. Although the Bill of Rights did not guarantee
freedom of conscience and in fact contained many expressions of
hostility to Catholics, there were still too few Jews in England
to attract determined opposition, and the Rational community went
unmolested. Both Spinoza's books and the writings of English
Jews were allowed to circulate freely, and, with Newton's
patronage, they did not escape the notice of the Royal Society.
Even in Holland, disapproval of Spinoza was no longer as strong
as it had once been. Most of the rabbis who had driven him from
the country thirty years since were long gone, and the
conservative reaction that had followed the fall of Jan de Witt
had long since run its course. The Jewish community had warmed
to Spinoza - at least somewhat - in the wake of On
Emancipation, and his writings on logic and empirical analysis
were gaining attention among Dutch natural philosophers.
Christiaan Huygens, in particular, was a long-standing
correspondent of Spinoza's, and circulated his works
enthusiastically among other Dutch thinkers. [FN4] Spinoza's
religious, as opposed to political and mathematical, ideas were
slower to gain a following, and the Jewish community of Holland
clung for the most part to traditional theology, but his name was
no longer anathema in Amsterdam.
In Palestine, the Rational colony in the Galilee was now more
than four thousand strong, and its growth was fueled by the
decree of the Elector of Brandenburg that any Jew applying for
permission to reside in the province was required to provide
passage to Palestine for three poor Jews. In the first year of
the decree, sixty-three Jews came to Palestine in this way, and
the expanding commercial opportunities of Berlin made it likely
that many more would follow. Most of these immigrants, who were
disproportionately uneducated servants and peddlers, were not
Rationalists, but many drifted into Rational observance after
settling in the Galilee colonies.
Their transformation was, perhaps, aided by the fact that
Rationalism in Palestine had been strongly influenced by the
mystics of nearby Safed. Many of the Galilee settlers chose to
reach Spinoza's "third knowledge" through meditation as well as
reason, and the readings used in the Palestine meeting halls
included passages from the Zohar. The Rationalists of Palestine
differed from their orthodox neighbors in custom and practice,
but their doctrines had converged substantially.
In Safed, the Rationalists had also gained some measure of
acceptance; the traditional Jewish community had been hard hit by
fire and disease, and the resources of the growing Rational
colonies were in great demand. By 1691, the excommunication of
the Rational community was all but forgotten in Safed; the
settlers brought their produce to market in the city, and two
Rational doctors established medical practices there during that
year. It seemed likely that within a generation, the two
communities would become one.
The ban still held in Jerusalem, though; the authority of the
rabbinate was stronger there, and the Jews of the holy city were
especially vigilant in guarding their traditions. The great
commentator Rabbi Avraham Amigo remained a staunch opponent of
Spinoza, and continued to warn the communities of Jerusalem and
Cairo against falling into Rational beliefs. Ironically,
Spinoza's greatest influence in those cities was among the
Muslims, who were free to disregard the rabbis' decree; his works
circulated freely within the Muslim communities of Palestine and
Egypt, and branches of the Rational Society existed in Cairo and
Alexandria. Indeed, the governor of Egypt was widely reputed to
be a member of the Society himself.
|
|
1691 was also
the year that Spinoza published his first major political work, The Measurement of Law. In the preface to this
book, Spinoza credited its inspiration both to ideas developed during
his correspondence with Locke and Newton and to a treatise released
by Ismet Celer the year before. This treatise, entitled The Civil Law, argued that the conformity of
government decrees with the principles of Islam could be measured by
their effect on the population. Since the intent of Islamic law was
to promote certain identifiable virtues, a statute could be measured
by the degree to which it increased these virtues and decreased the
corresponding vices. These virtues, naturally, included not only
individual piety but social justice and harmony. [FN5]
The Measurement of Law was, in many ways, an expansion on this
concept. It was also Spinoza's first attempt at applying
empirical methods to problems of ethics - which, as he had
explained to Locke, he regarded as matters touching upon both the
natural and the divine. His focus, he stated, was upon the
primary means by which human beings attempted to influence the
moral behavior of other humans: the law.
Like Celer, Spinoza argued that the effects of laws could be
measured against moral principles. These principles, whether
divinely revealed or derived through reason, would become the
standard by which laws were judged. Making such a judgment,
however, was rarely a simple matter, because few if any laws
affected only one social factor or affected all people uniformly.
How was one to weigh, for instance, a law that decreased poverty
but also decreased freedom, or one that made many people wealthy
but allowed others to starve? How were benefits and harms to be
weighed, and were there harms that no possible benefit could
justify? He discussed several possible methods of answering
these questions, many of which he would develop in later works.
Spinoza argued, as well, that the standards by which laws were
measured should affect the process of lawmaking. Since no law
could be moral unless it had both a moral purpose and a moral
effect, the lawmaking process should start with a clear statement
of the proposed statute's rationale - a measure which would,
incidentally, "promote due Consideration before the enactment of
Laws, and prevent unnecessary Statutes from being enacted
improvidently or in haste." Moreover, the first enactment of a
law should be for a limited period only, during which its
effects - both intended and unintended - could be carefully
studied. At the end of this period, the lawmaking body - or a
court - could rule on whether the statute served a moral purpose
and thus whether it should continue in force.
The first copies of The Measurement of Laws reached Hanover in
the summer, and found a receptive audience in the Duchess Sophia.
The treatise found a somewhat more critical audience in Leibniz,
who conceded that its principles were of interest but that it
was practically flawed. Spinoza had simply assumed that the
effects of laws were measurable, but Leibniz, with his greater
mathematical mind, realized that this was not necessarily true.
It was all well and good to state that a law that increased the
poverty of a nation was unjust, but how did one go about
determining whether a nation had been made richer or poorer? The
question of how societies could be measured intrigued Leibniz
greatly and, as he wrote to Spinoza late in the year, he was soon
hard at work on a theory of "social calculus." This theory,
which would be the subject of a number of Leibniz' later works,
was an important ancestor of the modern sciences of sociology and
statistics.
At the end of 1691, Spinoza was as happy as he had ever been in
his life - a man at the height of his faculties, the builder of
an edifice for the generations. In less than four years, it
would all come crashing down.
|
|
[FN1] In other words, on the same day as OTL. This wouldn't
necessarily happen in the ATL; battle is a chancy thing, and it's
entirely possible that Fazil Pasha's activities might be altered
enough that he'd avoid taking a bullet at Slankamen or fight the
Austrians someplace else entirely. On the other hand, Spinoza
didn't really play a part in the Grand Vizier's military reforms
and nothing has happened to change the general fortunes of war,
so the OTL outcome is also a reasonable possibility, and one
that has the advantage of keeping random effects to a minimum.
Thus far, I've generally held to the convention of keeping such
things as the outcome of battles and the deaths of historical
figures the same as OTL unless there's a good reason not to, and
I'll continue to do so for events such as the Constantinople
fires of 1693. (There's also the fact that I only get one
gimme, and I want to keep it available in case there's no other
way to achieve a certain result around 1710. One thousand points
to anyone other than Anthony who can tell me what result I
intend.)
[FN2] He's still a piker compared to Leibniz, who had more than
600 correspondents.
[FN3] It was rare, but not unknown, for Jewish women to practice
medicine at this time; see the "Medicine" part of the
bibliography at
.
As for the novel, I can somehow imagine that Sarah might feel
affinity for a philosopher's wife who had an only child.
[FN4] Huygens was a friend of Spinoza's in OTL; their
relationship in the ATL is somewhat more long-distance, but it
still exists.
[FN5] It's only natural that the original inspiration would come
in part from Celer and the Rational Society. As a commentator
recently stated about the 19th-century neo-Mu'tazilite scholar
Rashid Rida: "Since Rida... there has been particular interest
in the notion that obedience to the divinely revealed principles
of sharia leads inevitably to certain divinely-favored social
outcomes, such as social justice, chastity and democracy. If one
accepts such an axiom, one can determine whether laws conform to
the principles of sharia by determining whether the laws lead to
the divinely favored social ends." Clark Benner Lombardi,
Islamic Law as a Source of Constitutional Law in Egypt: The
Constitutionalization of the Sharia in a Modern Arab State, 37
Columbia J. Transnat'l L. 81, 95 (1998). Given that the neo-
Mu'tazilites are getting a 200-year head start in the ATL, it's
likely that one of them will pre-empt Rida with respect to this
utilitarian concept of law. Of course, Lombardi also notes that
this theory has been criticized as simplistic and overly
subjective, and the same criticisms will doubtless be applied to
Celer and Spinoza by some of their contemporaries.
|
|
|